REVISTA DE LA UNIVERSIDAD DEL ZULIA. 3ª época. Año 12 N° 34, 2021
Quite interesting is the position of M. Maduro, who states that:
“
We can identify four main sources of internal pluralism. First, there is a
plurality of constitutional sources (both European and national) which have
fed the EU constitutional framework and its general principles of law,
particularly as developed in the jurisprudence ofthe Court of Justice. Second,
the acceptance of the supremacy of EU rules over national constitutional
rules has not been unconditional, if not even, at times, resisted by national
constitutional courts. This confers to EU law a kind of contested or
negotiated normative authority. Third, there is an emergence of new forms of
power that challenges the traditional private/public distinction and the
different mechanisms of accountability associated to them. Such pluralism in
the forms of power challenges, in turn, the traditional legal categories upon
which EU rules have been framed. Fourth, the European Union is also
dominated by a form of political pluralism that can assume a rather radical
form since the conflicting political claims are often supported by
corresponding claims of polity authority” (Maduro, 2007).
In general, the author takes the view that the main purpose of constitutional
pluralism is to guarantee the integrity and coherence of the EU legal order. At the same
time, he identifies certain mandatory requirements set by constitutional pluralism to
achieve the above goal.
“
(
The first, requirement of EU constitutional pluralism is that ‘any legal order
national or European) must respect the identityof the other legal orders’, in
particular via the ‘recognition and adjustment of each legal order to the
plurality of equally legitimate claims of authority made by the other legal
orders’. The second requirement is that discourse among constitutional actors
must ‘take place in such a way as to promote the broadest participation
possible’. Third, the various actors in the European system must ‘share the
same commitment to a coherent legal order’, adjusting their claims to
authority in order to ensure consistency andvertical and horizontal
coherence. Fourth, national courts ought to justify their decisions on
‘
universalisable’ grounds that ‘could be applied by any other national court in
similar situations’. Fifth and finally, the principle of ‘institutional choice’
requiresthatconstitutional pluralism reject a singular focus on courts and
judgments, and instead recognize the actions of a broader range of
constitutional actors. So long as these requirements are fulfilled, it will
remain ‘possible to have a coherent legal order in acontext of competing
determinations of the law’ – conflicts over the ultimate locus of jurisdictional
authority need not be resolved” (Maduro, 2003).
It should also be noted that the concept of constitutional pluralism in the EU was
formed primarily in response to a number of cases in which the national constitutional
courts of EU member states sought to determine whether EU law is compatible with a
3
68